Daniel Dennett: How Does the Brain Store Beliefs?

2018-06-06 6

What if beliefs could be surgically inserted into a patient's brain? This is the basis of one of philosopher Daniel Dennett's thought experiments in exploration of how the brain represents beliefs. Dennett argues that individual beliefs are part of broader idea systems and that they couldn't possibly be stored like a library of belief sentences.

For the full playlist go to BigThink.com: http://bigthink.com/playlists/daniel-dennett-how-to-think-like-a-philosopher

Follow Big Think here:
YouTube: http://goo.gl/CPTsV5
Facebook: https://www.facebook.com/BigThinkdotcom
Twitter: https://twitter.com/bigthink

Transcript - One of the problems that's beset philosophers and cognitive scientists for the last 30, 40 years is how on earth the brain represents information. An eternally appealing idea is something like a language of thought that there's brain writing or mentalese and we write -- the brain writes sentences in mentalese that store the beliefs so that when you learn that giraffes are mammals, there's someplace in your brain where the word -- the mental word giraffe and the word mammal are tied together with a "is a" or something like that. So we have a big library of sentences. Those are our beliefs.
We have a belief box with lots of beliefs. That's an attractive idea of nice -- it has a certain simplicity that -- and we think we understand how sentences work to store information. Well now, if that were so, could a clever enough neurosurgeon wire in a false belief just out of the blue. So, let's imagine that our neurosurgeon decides to wire into our brain the belief that you have an older brother living in Cleveland. So he figures out how to write that in brainish and does all the microsurgery and there it is written in brainish in your brain.
Okay, you wake up from the anesthetic and so he says, "Yeah, do you have any siblings?" Well, if he's done his work well I guess the first thing you do is you say, "Yes, I have an older brother living in Cleveland." "Oh, what's his name?" And now what? Ah, ah, ah -- one of several things has to happen. Maybe you'll start confabulating and you'll say, umm, his name is Alfonso, and, um um he's a taxi driver, and he lives with his wife and two kids in the suburbs. That's one possibility. In other words, you couldn't just wire in one belief. You'd have to wire in something which generated a whole slew of beliefs. Alternatively, maybe you would say, "Oh my gosh. What did I just say? I said I had an older brother. I don't have an older brother. I have a sister or I'm an only child. What made me say that?" In that case, what we would see is that whatever the surgeon did, it wasn't wiring in a belief because as soon as you reflected on it, boom, it just vanished, it disappeared.
Well, if it's a belief then it's gotta be secured to a lot of other beliefs. That's just in the nature of belief. You can't have an isolated belief like I have an older brother living in Cleveland. If that state was one that you seem to be in, we'd want to explore it to see what came along with it. And either we would decide that you had some weird sort of growth in your brain that made you fixate on a sentence, sort of parrot like. And you'd say, "I'm an only child and I have an older brother living in Cleveland." Which, of course, would be contradicting yourself. What we wouldn't decide is that you believed you had an older brother living in Cleveland.
What this little thought experiment shows is that beliefs don't parcel themselves out the way sentences do. You could take any sentence on any topic and write it on any medium you like and put it in a drawer and there it would be. Beliefs aren't like that. They come in systems. They cohere in large clumps. This is sometimes called holism and there's still some theorists who think that holism is a bad idea. I think it's got to be the case. Holism is a good idea. That a particulate non-holistic theory of believe is a non-starter.
Directed / Produced by Jonathan Fowler, Elizabeth Rodd, and Dillon Fitton